[next] [prev] [up] Date: Thu, 23 Mar 95 00:29:47 -0500
[next] [prev] [up] From: Jerry Bryan <BRYAN@wvnvm.wvnet.edu >
~~~ ~~~ [up] Subject: Some Thoughts on Representative Elements

I would like to make some comments on representative elements, but
first there are some preliminaries.

In some of his recent notes, Martin Schoenert has carefully
distinguished between processes, operations, and states. For
the purposes of this note, I wish to distinguish between
processes and operations on the one hand, and states on the
other hand. For this one note alone, I will always use
upper case letters for processes and operations, and lower
case letters for states.

In functional notation, we often (e.g., calculus) see such things
as y=F(x). "Function" is synonymous with "operation", and I will
use the two terms somewhat interchangeably. In calculus, function
composition is often written something like y=FoG(x)=F(G(x)),
where the "o" is the best simulation I can do in E-mail of the
typical function composition symbol.

As has been discussed several times in this forum, the FoG type
of notation is interpreted right-to-left, but in group theory
we more typically write GF for function composition, and it is
interpreted left-to-right. With the left-to-right notation,
the function argument (if it is written) can be written on the
right as y=GF(x) or on the left as y=(x)GF. I gather that most
of Cube-Lovers do not like the latter convention, but I am
going to use it anyway. Indeed, as long as we are utterly
rigorous in our upper-case/lower-case convention, we can
dispense with the parentheses and write y=xGF (or simply
y=xF if the function F is a single function). Parentheses
can then be used for grouping without any ambiguity that they
might be denoting arguments.

We let G be the cube group and g be the set of cube states. We
can observe that each X in G is a function on g. Furthermore,
each X in G is a one-to-one function from g onto g. Hence,
each inverse X' exists. These facts are so obvious that they
are virtually never stated. But we are about to talk about
representative elements, and things are much less well behaved
when we talk about representatives.

One more preliminary: the idea that a state can be identified
with the operation which effects the state when applied to Start
can be expressed as x=iX. Hence, there is a one-to-one
correspondence between g and G, and we have |g|=|G|. Again,
things get much more unruly when we start talking about
representatives. Also, we can define the composition of the
states x and y as xy=(iX)(iY)=i(XY)=iXY, and this equation
defines an obvious isomorphism between g and G.

We will use * as the symbol for a selection function on the
M-conjugacy classes of g. We will write * as a postfix operator
so that it reads left-to-right with the rest of our operators.
We have x*=Repr{N'xN} for all N in M, the set of 48 rotations
and reflections.

Note that * is not uniquely determined. There are
approximately |M| ^ (|G| / |M|) possible choices for *, which is a
truly large number when compared with |G|. It is conceivable
that we might be able to prove some result for one particular
choice of * that would not be true for every choice of *. In
general, however, we will assume that * is fixed but arbitrary.

* is a function from g into (but not onto) g. We let g* be the
set of representative states, and * is a function from g onto g*.
The function * does not have an inverse, but if we consider * to
be a relation, then the inverse relation *' simply maps each
representative x* in g* back to the entire M-conjugacy class
of x*.

Consider the restriction of * to the set g*. At this point, *
is not very useful, because it is simply the identity.

Define the set Q* as

Q* = {F*, R*, L*, B*, U*, D*, F'*, R'*, L'*, B'*, U'*, D'*}

This set is near and dear to my heart, because it is how I obtain
nearly all my results. We will say more about inverses very soon,
but it should be observed immediately that it is not the case that
(F*)'=F'*, nor that (R*)'=R'*, etc.

Each of the twelve elements in Q* are functions from g into g*.
Much more interesting is the restriction of each element of Q*
to g*, so that they are functions from g* into g*. We are treating
each Q* as composed and not to be decomposed. You could think of
elements of g that are not also elements of g* appearing briefly
and virtually between the Q and the *, but each Q* is to be
treated as from g* into g* without being decomposed.

Can we do something like define the group G*=<Q*>? The answer
is no. I assume it will be totally obvious to many of you why not,
but I have to think about it for a bit. Martin commented that
the set of representatives could not be a group because the
number of representatives does not divide the size of G. But
it seems to me that Martin's argument only says that the representatives
are not a subgroup of G. It seems to me that it does not say that
there could not be a group constructed from the representatives.
But nonetheless, I think it is quite easy to show that there is
no way to make G* into a group.

Before I go on, I suspect that many of you will object to me using
the generator notation G*=<Q*>, even with the caveat that G* is not
a group. I probably agree, but I am not sure how else to convey
the same idea quite so compactly. I simply want to define G* as the
set of all compositions of elements of Q*. The compositions are
all well defined, although they behave terribly. And G* must be
finite, because g* is finite and there are only finitely many
functions that can be defined on a finite set.

I find the following argument that G* is not a group (and cannot
be made into a group) compelling, although there might well
be simpler arguments. Do any of the functions Q* have inverses?
In order to do so, they would have to be one-to-one from g* onto
g*. But i=i*, so i is in g*, and there is only one of the twelve
elements of Q* which maps onto i. Hence, at least eleven of the
twelve elements of Q* are not onto g*, and therefore do not have
inverses. It is trivial do choose * in such a way that all twelve
elements of Q* are not onto g*. However, I have not been able to
decide if there is way to choose * such that one of the elements
of Q* is onto g*. No doubt, somebody out there will have a
trivial proof one way or the other. In any case, the general lack
of inverses in Q* shows that G* cannot be made into a group.

Even though G* is not a group, it is nonetheless an interesting
structure. We can think of a "Cayley graph-like" structure where
we connect nodes in g* with arcs from Q*. I am not sure if such
a structure is properly called a Cayley graph, so just to be
safe I will call it a Cayley* graph.

As we have already seen, the identity state i*=i has only one
neighbor in our Cayley* graph. Are there any other such states?
Dan Hoey and Jim Saxe's _Symmetry and Local Maxima_ suggests
that there might be 72 such states, namely those states which
they call Q-transitive. A Q-transitive state has the characteristic
that all its neighbors are M-conjugate. However, some of the
Q-transitive states are themselves M-conjugate, so the 72 states
collapse somewhat in our Cayley* graph.

There are 4 states which are M-symmetric,
and these states are distinct in our Cayley* graph. There are
20 states which are H-symmetric but not M-symmetric, but these
states collapse into 10 states in our Cayley* graph. There are
48 states which are T-symmetric but not M-symmetric, but these
states collapse into 12 states in our Cayley* graph. Hence, there
are 26=4+10+12 nodes in our Cayley* graph which have only
one neighbor. These figures are given right at the end of _Symmetry
and Local Maxima_. They are also given by Martin Schoenert
in _Re: Re: Re: Re: Models of the Cube_ on 1 February 1995.

It has been thoroughly discussed that |X| = |X*| for all X in G.
But of more import for the way I build my data bases is the question
of whether for every x in g, will x* appear in my data base, given
that I generate the data base as i<Q*>. In other words, can any
x* of length n be decomposed into i(Q_1*)(Q_2*)...(Q_n*)? I find
this to be one of those things that is obvious yet is hard to
explain. Hence, I will borrow the following explanation that
was given to me by Dan Hoey. (Dan's version is much more elegant
than mine. Any crud in the following is mine, not Dan's.)

First of all, every x* in g* either is the identity or else has
a neighbor in g which is closer to Start. If it is the identity, it
is in (and indeed is the root of) the data base. Otherwise, we call
the neighbor y and calculate y*. Again, y* is either the identity
or else has a neighbor which is closer to Start. In this manner,
we can backtrack our way to Start from any x*. However, there is
not (yet) a guarantee that a forward search will find traverse
the same path forwards and find x*, and hence not (yet) a proof
that any of the path to x* except i itself is in the data base.

We note that if y is a neighbor of x in g, then it is immediate
that x is a neighbor of y as well. We need the same thing in g*
in order to get a forward search that corresponds to the backwards
search. That is, we need to show that if y* is a neighbor of x* in
g*, then x* is a neighbor of y*. We now show that if y* is a
neighbor of x* in g*, then x* is a neighbor of y* in g*.

Observe that if v* = w* (i.e., if v and w are M-conjugates), then
the neighbors of v and w are respective M-conjugates as well.
Assume x* is not the identity and let y be a neighbor which is
closer to Start. Then y* has a neighbor z with z*=x*. Hence, if
y* is in the data base, then x* is in the data base, and we have
neighbors in both directions.

I think of the preceding result as follows. Even though the functions
in G* are not individually ("locally") onto, the functions in G* are
collectively ("globally") onto. Hence, there is an arc _from_ every
node in the Cayley* graph, and there is an arc _to_ every node in the
Cayley* graph, and you can get from anywhere to anywhere in the graph.

The Cayley* graph is not a homomorphism of the Cayley graph (G* is
not a subgroup of G, and is not even a group), but I think of G* as
sort of passing the duck test for a homomorphism. That is, it
looks like a homomorphism and smells like homomorphism, even though
it isn't. (Personal opinion is that the duck test often fails in
this manner). But G* is a collapsing of G which does encode an
enormous amount of information about G.

Roughly speaking, there are two definitions of permutation. The
more informal definition is simply than a permutation is an
arrangement (or re-arrangement) of objects --- e.g., the number
of permutations of n objects taken r at a time. The more formal
definition is that a permutation is a function on a set which is
one-to-one and onto. Note that function on a finite set is
one-to-one if and only if it is onto, so in dealing with the
cube we can be a little sloppy at times and speak only of onto
or only of one-to-one.

All the elements in G are permutations and G is finite. It is
therefore trivial to show that for every X in G, there is
some integer n such that X^n=I. This means, among other things,
that there exists some integer n such that i(X^n)=i (from Start,
repeat a process enough times and you will return to Start) and
y(X^n)=y (from any position, repeat a process enough times and you
will return to the same position). The least such n for each
X is the order of X, and considerable discussion has occurred
in this forum concerning the order of various elements of G.

Once again, things become a bit more unruly when we talk about
G* instead of G. The elements of G* are not permutations because
they are not onto. So consider what happens when we calculate
something like (X*)^n. As a specific example, consider
i(R*)^n.

If iR*=r', then i(R*)^n simply oscillates back and forth between
i and r'. But if * is chosen so that iR* does not equal r', then
all bets are off. i(R*)^n will enter a loop eventually, but it
will never return to i. To understand its exact behavior, we would
have to be specific rather than arbitrary about the definition of *.
Similarly, x*(R*)^n might well never return to x*, but it would
loop eventually. These "eventual loops" rather remind me of
strange attractors.

My data bases are of the form i<Q*>, for example iR*L'*U'*R'*, etc.
As I have discussed before, backtracking through such a structure
is a bit tricky. Suppose, for example that you have x* in hand
and wish to backtrack to i. The way to do it that works best for
me is as follows: begin with x*; find x*(Q_1)* that is closer to
Start; find x*(Q_1)(Q_2)* that is closer to start (most definitely
NOT x*(Q_1)*(Q_2)*); find x*(Q_1)(Q_2)(Q_3)* that is closer to
Start (most definitely NOT x*(Q_1)*(Q_2)*(Q_3)*; etc. It is
doable in the fashion I said NOT to do, but it is extremely
tricky. You will have the sensation (as I have described before)
that your solution is rotating and reflecting out from under you.
The first way is much easier to keep up with.

Finally, how big is G*? Remember that g and G are the same size.
Write the restriction of G* to i as iG*. There is clearly a
one-to-one mapping between g* and iG*, and indeed we can identify
g* with iG* in the same manner in which we identify g with G.
But in iG*, all the elements of Q* are equivalent. When
we allow the domain of G* to be the entirety of g*, then the elements
of Q* are not equivalent. Hence, there are at least eleven more elements
in G* than in g*. I don't know how to calculate the size of G*. But
when Dan Hoey calculated the real size of the cube space, he
calculated the size of g*, not the size of G*.

 = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = = =
Robert G. Bryan (Jerry Bryan)                        (304) 293-5192
Associate Director, WVNET                            (304) 293-5540 fax
837 Chestnut Ridge Road                              BRYAN@WVNVM
Morgantown, WV 26505                                 BRYAN@WVNVM.WVNET.EDU

[next] [prev] [up] [top] [help]